Dictionary Definition
theoretical adj
1 concerned primarily with theories or hypotheses
rather than practical considerations; "theoretical science" [syn:
theoretic] [ant:
empirical]
2 concerned with theories rather than their
practical applications; "theoretical physics" [ant: applied]
3 based on specialized theory; "a theoretical
analysis" [syn: abstract]
User Contributed Dictionary
English
Adjective
- of or pertaining to theoretic studies (abstract, not empirical)
Related terms
Extensive Definition
The word theory has many distinct meanings in
different fields of knowledge, depending on their
methodologies and
the context of discussion.
In science a theory is a testable
model of
the manner of interaction of a set of natural
phenomena, capable of
predicting future occurrences or observations of the same kind, and
capable of being tested through experiment or otherwise
verified through empirical observation. For
the scientist,
"theory" is not in any way an antonym of "fact". For example,
it is a fact that an apple dropped on earth has been observed to
fall towards the center of the planet, and the theories commonly
used to describe and explain this behavior are Newton's theory of
universal
gravitation (see also gravitation), and the
general
theory of relativity.
In common usage, the word theory is often used to
signify a conjecture,
an opinion, a speculation, or a hypothesis. In this usage, a
theory is not necessarily based on facts; in other words, it is not
required to be consistent with true descriptions of reality. This usage of theory
leads to the common incorrect statements. True descriptions of
reality are more reflectively understood as statements
which would be true independently of what people think about
them.
According to the National Academy of Sciences,
Some scientific explanations are so well established that no new
evidence is likely to alter them. The explanation becomes a
scientific theory. In everyday language a theory means a hunch or
speculation. Not so in science. In science, the word theory refers
to a comprehensive explanation of an important feature of nature
that is supported by many facts gathered over time. Theories also
allow scientists to make predictions about as yet unobserved
phenomena.
Etymology
English attested since 1592, from Greek theoria (Jerome), Greek "contemplation, speculation", from "spectator", thea - "a view" + horan - "to see.", literally "looking at a show". There is a second possible etymology that traces the word back to to theion (divine things) instead of thea, reflecting the concept of contemplating the divine organisation (Cosmos) of the nature.Science
In scientific usage, a theory does not mean an unsubstantiated guess or hunch'', as it can in everyday speech. A theory is a logically self-consistent model or framework for describing the behavior of a related set of natural or social phenomena. It originates from or is supported by experimental evidence (see scientific method). In this sense, a theory is a systematic and formalized expression of all previous observations, and is predictive, logical, and testable. In principle, scientific theories are always tentative, and subject to corrections or inclusion in a yet wider theory. Commonly, many more specific hypotheses may be logically bound together by just one or two theories. As a rule for use of the term, theories tend to deal with much broader sets of universals than do hypotheses, which ordinarily deal with much more specific sets of phenomena or specific applications of a theory.Of several competing theories, one theory may be
superior to another in terms of its approximation of reality.
Scientific tests of the quality of a theory include its conformity
to known facts and its
ability to generate hypotheses with outcomes that would predict
further testable facts.
A difference in usage of the word "fact"
contributes to confusion in regard to the meaning of "theory." An
appreciation of the various meanings of "fact" and "knowledge" can
help to clarify an understanding of the meanings of "theory." (See
also: relativity of knowledge, under Relativism.)
The term theoretical
The term theoretical is sometimes informally used in lieu of hypothetical to describe a result which is predicted by theory but has not yet been adequately tested by observation or experiment. It is not uncommon for a theory to produce predictions which are later confirmed or proven incorrect by experiment. By inference, a prediction proved incorrect by experiment demonstrates that the hypothesis is invalid. This either means the theory is incorrect or that the experimental conjecture was wrong and the theory did not predict the hypothesis.In physics
In physics the term theory is generally used for a mathematical framework—derived from a small set of basic principles (usually symmetries - like equality of locations in space or in time, or identity of electrons, etc.)—which is capable of producing experimental predictions for a given category of physical systems. A good example is classical electromagnetism, which encompasses the results which can be derived from gauge symmetry (sometimes called gauge invariance) in a form of a few equations called Maxwell's equations. Note that the specific theoretical aspects of classical electromagnetic theory, which have been consistently and successfully replicated for well over a century, are termed "laws of electromagnetism", reflecting the fact that they are today taken for granted. Within electromagnetic theory generally, there are numerous hypotheses about how electromagnetism applies to specific situations. Many of these hypotheses are already considered to be adequately tested, with new ones always in the making and perhaps untested as yet.Currently unverifiable theories
The term theory is regularly stretched to refer to speculation which is currently unverifiable. Examples are string theory and various theories of everything. In the strict sense, the term theory should only be used when describing a model that is derived from experimental evidence and is provable (or disprovable). It is considered sufficient for the model to be in principle testable at some undetermined point in the future.Theories as "models"
Purpose
Theories are constructed in order to explain, predict and master phenomena (e.g. inanimate things, events, or the behaviour of animals). In many instances we are constructing models of reality. A theory makes generalizations about observations and consists of an interrelated, coherent set of ideas and models.Description and prediction
According to Stephen Hawking in A Brief History of Time, "a theory is a good theory if it satisfies two requirements: It must accurately describe a large class of observations on the basis of a model which contains only a few arbitrary elements, and it must make definite predictions about the results of future observations". He goes on to state, "any physical theory is always provisional, in the sense that it is only a hypothesis; you can never prove it. No matter how many times the results of experiments agree with some theory, you can never be sure that the next time the result will not contradict the theory. On the other hand, you can disprove a theory by finding even a single observation which disagrees with the predictions of the theory". The "unprovable by falsifiable" nature of theories is a consequence of the necessity of using inductive logic.Assumptions to formulate a theory
This is a view shared by Isaac Asimov. In Understanding Physics, Asimov spoke of theories as "arguments" where one deduces a "scheme" or model. Arguments or theories always begin with some premises—"arbitrary elements" as Hawking calls them (see above)—which are here described as "assumptions". An assumption according to Asimov issomething accepted without proof, and it is
incorrect to speak of an assumption as either true or false, since
there is no way of proving it to be either (If there were, it would
no longer be an assumption). It is better to consider assumptions
as either useful or useless, depending on whether deductions made
from them corresponded to reality. ... On the other hand, it seems
obvious that assumptions are the weak points in any argument, as
they have to be accepted on faith in a philosophy of science that
prides itself on its rationalism. Since we must start somewhere, we
must have assumptions, but at least let us have as few assumptions
as possible.
(See Occam's
Razor)
Example: Special Theory of Relativity
As an example of the use of assumptions to formulate a theory, consider how Albert Einstein put forth his Special Theory of Relativity. He took two phenomena which had been observed — that the "addition of velocities" is valid (Galilean transformation), and that light did not appear to have an "addition of velocities" (Michelson-Morley experiment). He assumed both observations to be correct, and formulated his theory, based on these assumptions, by simply altering the Galilean transformation to accommodate the lack of addition of velocities with regard to the speed of light. The model created in his theory is, therefore, based on the assumption that light maintains a constant velocity (or more commonly: the speed of light is a constant).Example: Ptolemy
An example of how theories are models can be seen from theories on the planetary system. The Greeks formulated theories which were recorded by the astronomer Ptolemy. In Ptolemy's planetary model, the earth was at the center, the planets and the sun made circular orbits around the earth, and the stars were on a sphere outside of the orbits of the planet and the earth. Retrograde motion of the planets was explained by smaller circular orbits of individual planets. This could be illustrated as a model, and could even be built into a literal model. Mathematical calculations could be made which predicted, to a great degree of accuracy, where the planets would be. His model of the planetary system survived for over 1500 years until the time of Copernicus. So one can see that a theory is a "model of reality," one which explains certain scientific facts; yet the theory may not be a satisfactory picture of reality. Another, more acceptable, theory can later replace the previous model, as when the Copernican theory replaced the Ptolemaic theory. Or a new theory can be used to modify an older theory as when Einstein modified Newtonian mechanics (which is still used for designing bridges and gasoline engines) with his theories of relativity.Differences between theory and model
Central to the nature of models, from general models to scale models, is the employment of representation (literally, "re-presentation") to describe particular aspects of a phenomenon or the manner of interaction among a set of phenomena. For instance, a scale model of a house or of a solar system is clearly not an actual house or an actual solar system; the aspects of an actual house or an actual solar system represented in a scale model are, only in certain limited ways, representative of the actual entity. In most ways that matter, the scale model of a house is not a house. Several commentators (e.g., Reese & Overton 1970; Lerner, 1998; Lerner & Teti, 2005, in the context of modeling human behavior) have stated that the important difference between theories and models is that the first is explanatory as well as descriptive, while the second is only descriptive (although still predictive in a more limited sense). General models and theories, according to philosopher Stephen Pepper (1948)—who also distinguishes between theories and models—are predicated on a "root" metaphor which constrains how scientists theorize and model a phenomenon and thus arrive at testable hypotheses.In engineering practice, a distinction is made
between "mathematical models" and "physical models".
Characteristics
The difference between science and unscientific nonsense was well caught in Wolfgang Pauli's famous comment on a paper he was shown: "This isn't right. It's not even wrong."Essential criteria
The defining characteristic of a scientific theory is that it makes falsifiable or testable predictions. The relevance, and specificity of those predictions determine how (potentially) useful the theory is. A would-be theory which makes no predictions which can be observed is not a useful theory. Predictions which are not sufficiently specific to be tested are similarly not useful. In both cases, the term "theory" is inapplicable.In practice a body of descriptions of knowledge is usually only
called a theory once it has a minimum empirical basis. That is, it:
- is consistent with pre-existing theory to the extent that the pre-existing theory was experimentally verified, though it will often show pre-existing theory to be wrong in an exact sense, and
- is supported by many strands of evidence rather than a single foundation, ensuring that it is probably a good approximation, if not totally correct.
Non-essential criteria
Additionally, a theory is generally only taken seriously if it:- is tentative, correctable and dynamic, in allowing for changes to be made as new data are discovered, rather than asserting certainty, and
- is the most parsimonious explanation, sparing in proposed entities or explanations, commonly referred to as passing the Occam's razor test.
This is true of such established theories as
special
and general
relativity, quantum
mechanics, plate
tectonics, evolution, etc. Theories
considered scientific meet at least most, but ideally all, of these
extra criteria.
Theories do not have to be perfectly accurate to
be scientifically useful. The predictions made by Classical
mechanics are known to be inaccurate, but they are sufficiently
good approximations in most circumstances that they are still very
useful and widely used in place of more accurate but mathematically
difficult theories.
Indistinguishable theories
Sometimes it happens that two theories are found to make exactly the same predictions. In this case, they are indistinguishable, and the choice between them reduces to which is the more convenient.Criterion for scientific status
Karl Popper described the characteristics of a scientific theory as follows:- It is easy to obtain confirmations, or verifications, for nearly every theory—if we look for confirmations.
- Confirmations should count only if they are the result of risky predictions; that is to say, if, unenlightened by the theory in question, we should have expected an event which was incompatible with the theory—an event which would have refuted the theory.
- Every "good" scientific theory is a prohibition: it forbids certain things to happen. The more a theory forbids, the better it is.
- A theory which is not refutable by any conceivable event is non-scientific. Irrefutability is not a virtue of a theory (as people often think) but a vice.
- Every genuine test of a theory is an attempt to falsify it, or to refute it. Testability is falsifiability; but there are degrees of testability: some theories are more testable, more exposed to refutation, than others; they take, as it were, greater risks.
- Confirming evidence should not count except when it is the result of a genuine test of the theory; and this means that it can be presented as a serious but unsuccessful attempt to falsify the theory. (I now speak in such cases of "corroborating evidence".)
- Some genuinely testable theories, when found to be false, are still upheld by their admirers—for example by introducing ad hoc some auxiliary assumption, or by reinterpreting the theory ad hoc in such a way that it escapes refutation. Such a procedure is always possible, but it rescues the theory from refutation only at the price of destroying, or at least lowering, its scientific status. (I later describe such a rescuing operation as a "conventionalist twist" or a "conventionalist stratagem".)
One can sum up all this by saying that according
to Popper, the criterion of the scientific status of a theory is
its falsifiability, or refutability, or testability.
Several philosophers and historians of science
have, however, argued that Popper's definition of theory as a set
of falsifiable statements is wrong because, as Philip
Kitcher has pointed out, if one took a strictly Popperian view
of "theory", observations of Uranus when first discovered in 1781
would have "falsified" Newton's celestial mechanics. Rather, people
suggested that another planet influenced Uranus'
orbit—and this prediction was indeed eventually
confirmed. Kitcher agrees with Popper that "there is surely
something right in the idea that a science can succeed only if it
can fail". He also takes into account Hempel and Quine's critiques
of Popper, to the effect that scientific theories include
statements that cannot be falsified (presumably what Hawking
alluded to as arbitrary elements), and the point that good theories
must also be creative. He insists that we view scientific theories
as consisting of an "elaborate collection of statements", some of
which are not falsifiable, while others—those he calls
"auxiliary hypotheses", are.
According to Kitcher, good scientific theories
must have three features:
- Unity: "A science should be unified…. Good theories consist of just one problem-solving strategy, or a small family of problem-solving strategies, that can be applied to a wide range of problems" (1982: 47).
- Fecundity: "A great scientific theory, like Newton's, opens up new areas of research…. Because a theory presents a new way of looking at the world, it can lead us to ask new questions, and so to embark on new and fruitful lines of inquiry…. Typically, a flourishing science is incomplete. At any time, it raised more questions than it can currently answer. But incompleteness is not vice. On the contrary, incompleteness is the mother of fecundity…. A good theory should be productive; it should raise new questions and presume that those questions can be answered without giving up its problem-solving strategies" (1982: 47–48).
- Auxiliary hypotheses that are independently testable: "An auxiliary hypothesis ought to be testable independently of the particular problem it is introduced to solve, independently of the theory it is designed to save" (1982: 46) (e.g. the evidence for the existence of Neptune is independent of the anomalies in Uranus's orbit).
Like other definitions of theories, including
Popper's, Kitcher makes it clear that a good theory includes
statements that have (in his terms) "observational consequences".
But, like the observation of irregularities in the orbit of Uranus,
falsification is only one possible consequence of observation. The
production of new hypotheses is another possible—and
equally important—observational consequence.
Mathematics
In mathematics, the word theory is used informally to refer to certain distinct bodies of knowledge about mathematics. This knowledge consists of axioms, definitions, theorems and computational techniques, all related in some way by tradition or practice. Examples include group theory, set theory, Lebesgue integration theory and field theory.The term
theory also has a precise technical usage in mathematics,
particularly in mathematical
logic and model
theory. A theory in this sense is a set of statements in a
formal
language, which is closed
under application of certain procedures called rules of
inference. A special case of this, an axiomatic theory,
consists of axioms (or
axiom schemata) and rules of inference. A theorem is a statement which can
be derived from those axioms by application of these rules of
inference. Theories used in applications are abstractions of observed
phenomena and the resulting theorems provide solutions to
real-world problems. Obvious examples include arithmetic (abstracting
concepts of number), geometry (concepts of space),
and probability
(concepts of randomness and likelihood).
Gödel's incompleteness theorem shows that no consistent, recursively
enumerable theory (that is, one whose theorems form a
recursively enumerable set) in which the concept of natural
numbers can be expressed, can include all true statements about them. As a
result, some domains of knowledge cannot be formalized, accurately
and completely, as mathematical theories. (Here, formalizing
accurately and completely means that all true
propositions—and only true propositions—are
derivable within the mathematical system.) This limitation,
however, in no way precludes the construction of mathematical
theories which formalize large bodies of scientific
knowledge.
Other fields
Theories exist not only in the so-called hard sciences, but in all fields of academic study, from philosophy to music to literature.List of notable theories
- Astronomy: Big Bang Theory
- Biology: Cell theory — Evolution
- Chemistry: Atomic theory — Kinetic theory of gases
- Climatology: Theory of Global Climate Change (due to anthropogenic activity)
- Computer science: Algorithmic information theory — Computation theory
- Economics: Decision theory
- Education: Constructivist theory — Critical pedagogy theory — Education theory — Multiple intelligence theory — Progressive education theory
- Engineering: Circuit theory — Control theory — Signal theory — Systems theory
- Film: Film Theory
- Games: Game theory — Rational choice theory
- Geology: Plate tectonics
- Humanities: Critical theory
- Literature: Literary theory
- Mathematics: Catastrophe theory — Category theory — Chaos theory — Graph theory — Knot theory — Number theory — Probability theory — Set theory
- Music: Music theory
- Philosophy: Proof theory — Speculative reason — Theory of truth — Type theory — Value theory — Virtue theory
- Physics: Acoustic theory — Antenna theory — General relativity — Special relativity — Theory of relativity — Quantum field theory
- Planetary science: Giant impact theory
- Visual Art: Aesthetics — Art Educational theory — Architecture — Composition — Anatomy — Color theory — Perspective — Visual perception — Geometry — Manifolds
- Sociology: Sociological theory — Social theory — Critical theory
- Statistics : Extreme value theory
- Theatre : Theory relating to theatrical performance.
- Other: Obsolete scientific theories — Phlogiston theory
Scientific laws
Scientific laws are similar to scientific theories in that they are principles which can be used to predict the behavior of the natural world. Both scientific laws and scientific theories are typically well-supported by observations and/or experimental evidence. Usually scientific laws refer to rules for how nature will behave under certain conditions. Scientific theories are more overarching explanations of how nature works and why it exhibits certain characteristics.Notes
References
- Popper, Karl (1963), Conjectures and Refutations, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, UK, pp. 33–39. Reprinted in Theodore Schick (ed., 2000), Readings in the Philosophy of Science, Mayfield Publishing Company, Mountain View, CA, pp. 9–13.
- Chairman of Biology and Kennesaw State Ronald Matson's webpage comparing scientific laws and theories
- Hawking, Stephen (1996). "The Illustrated A Brief History of Time" (Updated and expanded ed.). New York: Bantam Books, p. 15.
- Mohr, Johnathon (2008). "Revelations and Implications of the Failure of Pragmatism: The Hijacking of Knowledge Creation by the Ivory Tower". New York: Ballantine Books. pp. 87-192.
See also
theoretical in Arabic: نظرية
theoretical in Bulgarian: Теория
theoretical in Bosnian: Teorija
theoretical in Catalan: Teoria
theoretical in Czech: Teorie
theoretical in Danish: Teori
theoretical in German: Theorie
theoretical in Esperanto: Teorio
theoretical in Spanish: Teoría
theoretical in Estonian: Teooria
theoretical in Persian: نظریه
theoretical in Finnish: Teoria
theoretical in French: Théorie
theoretical in Galician: Teoría
theoretical in Hebrew: תאוריה
theoretical in Croatian: Teorija
theoretical in Indonesian: Teori
theoretical in Ido: Teorio
theoretical in Icelandic: Kenning
theoretical in Italian: Teoria
theoretical in Japanese: 理論
theoretical in Korean: 이론
theoretical in Lithuanian: Teorija
theoretical in Latvian: Teorija
theoretical in Macedonian: Теорија
theoretical in Dutch: Theorie
theoretical in Norwegian Nynorsk: Teori
theoretical in Norwegian: Teori
theoretical in Polish: Teoria
theoretical in Portuguese: Teoria
theoretical in Quechua: Ñasa
theoretical in Romanian: Teorie
theoretical in Russian: Теория
theoretical in Serbo-Croatian: Teorija
theoretical in Simple English: Theory
theoretical in Slovak: Teória
theoretical in Slovenian: Teorija
theoretical in Albanian: Teoria
theoretical in Serbian: Теорија
theoretical in Swedish: Teori
theoretical in Telugu: సిద్ధాంతము
theoretical in Thai: ทฤษฎี
theoretical in Turkish: Kuram
theoretical in Ukrainian: Теорія
theoretical in Uzbek: Nazariya
theoretical in Vietnamese: Lý thuyết
theoretical in Yiddish: טעאריע
theoretical in Chinese: 理論
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
abstract, academic, analytical, armchair, closet, conceptual, conjectural, debatable, fanciful, hypothetic, hypothetical, ideal, idealized, ideational, ideological, impractical, moot, notional, postulatory, problematical, pure, putative, speculative, suppositional, supposititious, transcendent, transcendental, unproved, unproven, unrealistic, untested